Toggle navigation
CEPA.INFO
FAQ
BROWSE
Authors
Constructivist Approaches
Background Disciplines
Reading Lists
Latest Fulltext Additions
LOGIN
Journal
Journal of Consciousness Studies
Publications Found:
61
·
Show All Abstracts
·
Highlight Matches
Search CEPA
» Help with Search
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x2f���������������������������������������������������������������������������������B
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x2f������������������������������������������������������������������������������
fulltext:"Man, having within himself an imagined world of lines and numbers, operates in it with abstractions just as God in the universe, did with reality"
fulltext:"Man, having within himself an imagined world of lines and numbers, operates in it with abstractions just as God in the universe, did with reality"
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????? ORDER BY 3989
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/?????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????) ORDER BY 7543
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/?????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????' ORDER BY 4180
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/?????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????') ORDER BY 4953
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/?????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????' ORDER BY 7206
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????? ORDER BY 8748
By default, Find returns all publications that contain the words in the surnames of their author, in their titles, or in their years. For example,
Maturana
finds all publications authored by Maturana and publications that have "Maturana" in their title
Maturana 1974
finds all publications authored by Maturana in 1974
You can directly search for a reference by copy-pasting it. For example,
Glasersfeld E. von (1974) Jean Piaget and the radical constructivist epistemology
Unless a word (or phrase) if prefixed with a minus (-) it must be present in all results. Examples:
Glasersfeld Varela
shows all publications Ernst von Glasersfeld and Francisco Varela wrote together.
Glasersfeld "Jean Piaget"
finds all publications with
Glasersfeld
and
Jean Piaget
in it.
Prefix with
-
to indicate that this word must not be present in any result:
cognition -biology
will find entries that have
cognition
in the title but not
biology
.
Enter the surname of an author and a year to find all publications the author wrote in that year:
Glasersfeld 1995
presents all publications Ernst von Glasersfeld published in 1995.
Use
*
to match any characters:
constructivis*
matches constructivism and constructivist.
Enclose phrases between double quotes
"
to force phrase search:
"biology of cognition"
lists only the publications containing this phrase. Without the double quotes it will return all publications containing "biology" and all publications containing "cognition".
All the searches above match author names, titles and years. You can also address single fields:
author:glasersfeld title:reality
shows publications von Glasersfeld wrote on reality;
abstract:second-order
searches all abstracts for "second-order";
editor:Watzlawick
finds all books edited by Watzlawick.
Note there is no space after the colon.
Attention: Words of three letters and less are ignored.
"Not one, not two"
will return no result although there is
Varela's paper
of this title.
Ataria Y. (2017) The answer to the ultimate question of life, the universe, and everything: Or some reflections on the feasibility of the neurophenomenology research programme. Journal of Consciousness Studies 24(1–2): 7–30. https://cepa.info/7757
Ataria Y.
(
2017
)
The answer to the ultimate question of life, the universe, and everything: Or some reflections on the feasibility of the neurophenomenology research programme
.
Journal of Consciousness Studies
24(1–2): 7–30.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/7757
Copy Citation
In 1996 Varela established the neurophenomenology research programme (NRP). This project was not designed to solve what Chalmers has defined as the hard problem, but rather to offer a methodological remedy for this problem. The NRP seeks to bridge the explanatory gap by creating a reciprocal dialogue between the firstperson perspective on the one hand and third-person perspective on the other. Yet, twenty years after Varela’s NRP kicked off, it seems that the explanatory gap is still very much alive. This paper argues that as long as subjective experience remains at least somewhat inaccessible, we will not be able to bridge this gap.
Bitbol M. & Petitmengin C. (2011) On life beneath the subject/object duality: A reply to Pierre Steiner. Journal of Consciousness Studies 18(2): 125–127. https://cepa.info/4448
Bitbol M.
&
Petitmengin C.
(
2011
)
On life beneath the subject/object duality: A reply to Pierre Steiner
.
Journal of Consciousness Studies
18(2): 125–127.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/4448
Copy Citation
Bitbol M. & Petitmengin C. (2011) On pure reflection: A reply to Dan Zahavi. Journal of Consciousness Studies 18(2): 24–37. https://cepa.info/4449
Bitbol M.
&
Petitmengin C.
(
2011
)
On pure reflection: A reply to Dan Zahavi
.
Journal of Consciousness Studies
18(2): 24–37.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/4449
Copy Citation
Carruthers P. (2017) The illusion of conscious thought. Journal of Consciousness Studies 24(9–10): 228–252. https://cepa.info/7364
Carruthers P.
(
2017
)
The illusion of conscious thought
.
Journal of Consciousness Studies
24(9–10): 228–252.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/7364
Copy Citation
This paper argues that episodic thoughts (judgments, decisions, and so forth) are always unconscious. Whether consciousness is understood in terms of global broadcasting/widespread accessibility or in terms of non-interpretive higher-order awareness, the conclusion is the same: there is no such thing as conscious thought. Arguments for this conclusion are reviewed. The challenge of explaining why we should all be under the illusion that our thoughts are often conscious is then taken up.
Key words:
attention
,
confabulation
,
consciousness
,
self-knowledge
,
thought
,
working memory.
Clark A. (1999) Visual awareness and visuomotor action. Journal of Consciousness Studies 6(11–12): 1–18. https://cepa.info/2266
Clark A.
(
1999
)
Visual awareness and visuomotor action
.
Journal of Consciousness Studies
6(11–12): 1–18.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/2266
Copy Citation
Recent work in "embodied, embedded" cognitive science links mental contents to large-scale distributed effects: dynamic patterns implicating elements of (what are traditionally seen as) sensing, reasoning and acting. Central to this approach is an idea of biological cognition as profoundly "action-oriented" - geared not to the creation of rich, passive inner models of the world, but to the cheap and efficient production of real-world action in real-world context. A case in point is Hurley's (1998) account of the profound role of motor output in fixing the contents of conscious visual awareness – an account that also emphasizes distributed vehicles and long-range dynamical loops. Such stories can seem dramatically opposed to accounts, such as Milner and Goodale (1995), that stress relatively local mechanisms and that posit firm divisions between processes of visual awareness and of visuomotor action. But such accounts, I argue, can be deeply complimentary and together illustrate an important lesson. The lesson is that cognition may be embodied and action-oriented in two distinct – but complimentary – ways. There is a way of being embodied and action-oriented that implies being closely geared to the fine-grained control of low level effectors (hands, arms, legs and so on). And there is a way of being embodied and action-oriented that implies being closely geared to gross motor intentions, current goals, and schematic motor plans. Human cognition, I suggest, is embodied and action- oriented in both these ways. But the neural systems involved, and the size and scope of the key dynamic loops, may be quite different in each case.
Davies T. N., Hoffman D. D. & Rodriguez A. M. (2002) Visual worlds: Construction or reconstruction. Journal of Consciousness Studies 9(5–6): 72–87. https://cepa.info/6226
Davies T. N.
,
Hoffman D. D.
&
Rodriguez A. M.
(
2002
)
Visual worlds: Construction or reconstruction
.
Journal of Consciousness Studies
9(5–6): 72–87.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/6226
Copy Citation
Psychophysical studies of change blindness indicate that, at any instant, human observers are aware of detail in few parts of the visual field. Such results suggest, to some theorists, that human vision reconstructs only a few portions of the visual scene and that, to bridge the resulting representational gaps, it often lets physical objects serve as their own short-term memory. We propose that human vision reconstructs no portion of the visual scene, and that it never lets physical objects serve as their own short-term memory.
De Jaegher H. (2015) How we affect each other: Michel Henry’s “pathos-with” and the enactive approach to intersubjectivity. Journal of Consciousness Studies 22(1–2): 112–132. https://cepa.info/5641
De Jaegher H.
(
2015
)
How we affect each other: Michel Henry’s “pathos-with” and the enactive approach to intersubjectivity
.
Journal of Consciousness Studies
22(1–2): 112–132.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/5641
Copy Citation
What makes it possible to affect one another, to move and be moved by another person? Why do some of our encounters transform us? The experience of moving one another points to the inter-affective in intersubjectivity. Inter-affection is hard to account for under a cognitivist banner, and has not received much attention in embodied work on intersubjectivity. I propose that understanding inter-affection needs a combination of insights into self-affection, embodiment, and interaction processes. I start from Michel Henry’s radically immanent idea of self-affection, and bring it into a contrastive dialogue with the enactive concepts of autonomy and (participatory) sense-making. I suggest that the latter ideas can open up Henry’s idea of self-affection to inter-affection (something he aimed to do, but did not quite manage) and that, in turn, Henry’s work can provide insights into underexplored elements of intersubjectivity, such as its ineffable and mysterious aspects, and erotic encounters
Key words:
michel henry
,
affect
,
enaction
,
ineffability
,
inter-affection
,
interactive experience
,
intersubjectivity
,
participatory sense-making
,
self-affection
,
sexuality
,
social interaction
de Waal F., Thompson E. & Proctor J. (2005) Primates, Monks, and the Mind: The Case of Empathy. Journal of Consciousness Studies 12(7): 38–54. https://cepa.info/2360
de Waal F.
,
Thompson E.
&
Proctor J.
(
2005
)
Primates, Monks, and the Mind: The Case of Empathy
.
Journal of Consciousness Studies
12(7): 38–54.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/2360
Copy Citation
Depraz N. (1999) The phenomenological reduction as praxis. Journal of Consciousness Studies 6(2–3): 95–110. https://cepa.info/5699
Depraz N.
(
1999
)
The phenomenological reduction as praxis
.
Journal of Consciousness Studies
6(2–3): 95–110.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/5699
Copy Citation
Excerpt:
This paper is concerned with the method of phenomenological reduction understood as a disciplined embodied practice. However before we embark in the discussion that gives this paper its title, it is essential to provide the context from which these questions sprang at the turn of the century, when phenomenology was founded.
Foglia L. & Grush R. (2011) The limitations of a purely enactive (non-representational) account of imagery. Journal of Consciousness Studies 18(5–6): 35–43. https://cepa.info/5606
Foglia L.
&
Grush R.
(
2011
)
The limitations of a purely enactive (non-representational) account of imagery
.
Journal of Consciousness Studies
18(5–6): 35–43.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/5606
Copy Citation
Enaction, as put forward by Varela and defended by other thinkers (notably Alva Noë, 2004; Susan Hurley, 2006; and Kevin O’Regan, 1992), departs from traditional accounts that treat mental processes (like perception, reasoning, and action) as discrete, independent processes that are causally related in a sequen- tial fashion. According to the main claim of the enactive approach, which Thompson seems to fully endorse, perceptual awareness is taken to be a skill-based activity. Our perceptual contact with the world, according to the enactionists, is not mediated by representations but is enacted, and the notion of representation, belonging to the classic computational paradigm, has no place in this alternative approach. Though Thompson does not pronounce directly on the issue of representationalism, he is most definitely keeping the company of anti-representationalists, and in that context it is not unreasonable to take his silence for consent. In this paper, we will argue that the enactive approach to imagery is unworkable unless it makes appeal to representations, understood in a particular way. Not understood as pictures, to be sure. Or sentences for that matter. But those aren’t the only options.
Key words:
imagination
,
enactive theory of perception
,
representation≤ forward models
,
emulators
Export result page as:
CF Format
·
APA
·
BibTex
·
EndNote
·
Harvard
·
MLA
·
Nature
·
RIS
·
Science
Page
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
Please provide us with your
feedback/evaluation/suggestions