Abramova K. & Villalobos M. (2015) The apparent (ur-)intentionality of living beings and the game of content. Philosophia 43(3): 651–668. https://cepa.info/6635
Abramova K. & Villalobos M.
(
2015)
The apparent (ur-)intentionality of living beings and the game of content.
Philosophia 43(3): 651–668.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/6635
Hutto and Satne, Philosophia (2014) propose to redefine the problem of naturalizing semantic content as searching for the origin of content instead of attempting to reduce it to some natural phenomenon. The search is to proceed within the framework of Relaxed Naturalism and under the banner of teleosemiotics which places Ur-intentionality at the source of content. We support the proposed redefinition of the problem but object to the proposed solution. In particular, we call for adherence to Strict Naturalism and replace teleosemiotics with autopoietic theory of living beings. Our argument for these adjustments stems from our analysis of the flagship properties of Ur-intentionality: specificity and directedness. We attempt to show that the first property is not unique to living systems and therefore poses a problem of where to place a demarcation line for the origin of content. We then argue that the second property is a feature ascribed to living systems, not their intrinsic part and therefore does not form a good foundation for the game of naturalizing content. In conclusion we suggest that autopoietic theory can not only provide a competitive explanation of the basic responding of pre-contentful organisms but also clarify why Ur-intentionality is attributed to them in such an intuitive manner.
Bitbol M. (1998) Some steps towards a transcendental deduction of quantum mechanics. Philosophia Naturalis 35: 253–280. https://cepa.info/3658
Bitbol M.
(
1998)
Some steps towards a transcendental deduction of quantum mechanics.
Philosophia Naturalis 35: 253–280.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/3658
Excerpt: My purpose in this paper is to show that the two major options on which the current debate on the interpretation of quantum mechanics relies, namely realism and empiricism (or instrumentalism), are far from being exhaustive. There is at least one more position available; a position which has been widely known in the history of philosophy during the past two centuries but which, in spite of some momentous exceptions, has only attracted little interest until recently in relation to the foundational problems of quantum mechanics. According to this third position, one may provide a theory with much stronger justifications than mere a posteriori empirical adequacy, without invoking the slightest degree of isomorphism between this theory and the elusive things out there. Such an intermediate attitude, which is metaphysically as agnostic as empiricism, but which shares with realism a commitment to considering the structure of theories as highly significant, has been named transcendentalism after Kant. Of course, I have no intention in this paper to rehearse the procedures and concepts developed by Kant himself; for these particular procedures and concepts were mostly adapted to the state of physics in his time, namely to Newtonian mechanics. I rather wish to formulate a generalized version of his method and show how this can yield a reasoning that one is entitled to call a transcendental deduction of quantum mechanics. This will be done in three steps. To begin with, I shall define carefully the word “transcendental,” and the procedure of “transcendental deduction,” in terms which will make clear how they can have a much broader field of application than Kant ever dared to imagine. Then, I shall show briefly that the main structural features of quantum mechanics can indeed be transcendentally deduced in this modern sense. Finally, I shall discuss the significance, and also the limits, of these results.
Colombetti G. (2017) The embodied and situated nature of moods. Philosophia. 45: 1437–1451. https://cepa.info/6916
Colombetti G.
(
2017)
The embodied and situated nature of moods.
Philosophia. 45: 1437–1451.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/6916
In this paper I argue that it is misleading to regard the brain as the physical basis or “core machinery” of moods. First, empirical evidence shows that brain activity not only influences, but is in turn influenced by, physical activity taking place in other parts of the organism (such as the endocrine and immune systems). It is therefore not clear why the core machinery of moods ought to be restricted to the brain. I propose, instead, that moods should be conceived as embodied, i.e., their physical basis should be enlarged so as to comprise not just brain but also bodily processes. Second, I emphasise that moods are also situated in the world. By this I do not simply mean that moods are influenced by the world, but that they are complexly interrelated with it, in at least three different ways: they are shaped by cultural values and norms; they are materially and intersubjectively “scaffolded”; and they can even “experientially incorporate” parts of the world, i.e., include the experience of parts of the world as part of oneself.
Diettrich O. (1997) Kann es eine ontologiefreie evolutionäre Erkenntnistheorie geben? Philosophia naturalis 34(1): 71–105. https://cepa.info/3914
Diettrich O.
(
1997)
Kann es eine ontologiefreie evolutionäre Erkenntnistheorie geben?.
Philosophia naturalis 34(1): 71–105.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/3914
Most of what nowadays is called evolutionary epistemology tries to explain the phylogenetic acquisition of inborn ‘knowledge’ and the evolution of the mental instruments concerned – mostly in terms of adaptation to external conditions. These conditions, however, cannot be described but in terms of what is provided by the mental instruments which are said to be brought about just by these conditions themselves. So they cannot be defined in an objective and non-circular way. This problem is approached here by what is called the
Gutmann W. F. & Weingarten M. (1991) Maschinentheoretische Grundlagen der organismischen Konstruktionslehre. Philosophia naturalis 28: 231–256.
Gutmann W. F. & Weingarten M.
(
1991)
Maschinentheoretische Grundlagen der organismischen Konstruktionslehre.
Philosophia naturalis 28: 231–256.
Northoff G. (2001) Was ist Neurophilosophie? Philosophia naturalis 38(2): 205–244. https://cepa.info/3918
Northoff G.
(
2001)
Was ist Neurophilosophie?.
Philosophia naturalis 38(2): 205–244.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/3918
In jüngerer Zeit greifen philosophische Untersuchungen zum Leib-Seele-Problem zunehmend Ergebnisse aus den Neurowissenschaften auf und verknüpfen diese mit philosophischen Begrifflichkeiten. Solch eine Verknüpfung von Philosophie und Neurowissenschaft wird häufig unter dem Begriff “Neurophilosophie” subsumiert, ohne dass dieser Begriff und das damit verknüpfte methodische Vorgehen näher beleuchtet oder explizit diskutiert werden. Ziel des vorliegenden Aufsatzes ist es daher, sowohl den Begriff der “Neurophilosophie” als auch das hierfür spezifische methodische Vorgehen zu definieren und programmatisch näher zu charakterisieren.
Penzlin H. (2002) Warum das Autopoiese-Konzept Maturanas die Organisation lebendiger Systeme unzutreffend beschreibt [Why Maturana\s autopoiesis concept incorrectly describes the organization of living systems]. Philosophia Naturalis 39(1): 61–87. https://cepa.info/4857
Penzlin H.
(
2002)
Warum das Autopoiese-Konzept Maturanas die Organisation lebendiger Systeme unzutreffend beschreibt [Why Maturana's autopoiesis concept incorrectly describes the organization of living systems].
Philosophia Naturalis 39(1): 61–87.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/4857
Excerpt: Maturana envisions a comprehensive theory that makes both the cognitive subject in its “functional organization” and the cognitive performance produced by this subject equally understandable. The aim of this article is to examine Maturana and Varela’s autopoiesis concept, which refers to biological facts and provides the basis for all further considerations, for its sustainability from the biological perspective.
Reithmayr F. (1989) Die Innenwelt der Aussenwelt der Innenwelt. Bemerkungen zu Glasersfeld. Prima Philosophia 2: 339–352. https://cepa.info/4780
Reithmayr F.
(
1989)
Die Innenwelt der Aussenwelt der Innenwelt. Bemerkungen zu Glasersfeld.
Prima Philosophia 2: 339–352.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/4780
Ziemke A. (1994) Teleologie der Wahrnehmung. Philosophia Naturalis 31(2): 263–292.
Ziemke A.
(
1994)
Teleologie der Wahrnehmung.
Philosophia Naturalis 31(2): 263–292.
Export result page as:
·
·
·
·
·
·
·
·