Zahavi D. (2002) First-person thoughts and embodied self-awareness: Some reflections on the relation between recent analytical philosophy and phenomenology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 7–26.
The article examines some of the main theses about self-awareness developed in recent analytic philosophy of mind (especially the work of Bermúdez), and points to a number of striking overlaps between these accounts and the ones to be found in phenomenology. Given the real risk of unintended repetitions, it is argued that it would be counterproductive for philosophy of mind to ignore already existing resources, and that both analytical philosophy and phenomenology would profit from a more open exchange.
Zahavi D. (2016) The end of what? Phenomenology vs. speculative realism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 24(3): 289–309. https://cepa.info/6986
Phenomenology has recently come under attack from proponents of speculative realism. In this paper, I present and assess the criticism, and argue that it is either superficial and simplistic or lacks novelty.
Recently, a number of neuroscientists and philosophers have taken the so-called predictive coding approach to support a form of radical neuro-representationalism, according to which the content of our conscious experiences is a neural construct, a brain-generated simulation. There is remarkable similarity between this account and ideas found in and developed by German neo-Kantians in the mid-nineteenth century. Some of the neo-Kantians eventually came to have doubts about the cogency and internal consistency of the representationalist framework they were operating within. In this paper, I will first argue that some of these concerns ought to be taken seriously by contemporary proponents of predictive coding. After having done so, I will turn to phenomenology. As we shall see, Husserl’s endorsement of transcendental idealism was partially motivated by his rejection of representationalism and phenomenalism and by his attempt to safeguard the objectivity of the world of experience. This confronts us with an intriguing question. Which position is best able to accommodate our natural inclination for realism: Contemporary neuro-representationalism or Husserl’s transcendental idealism?
Zaslawski N. (2018) Neurodialectics: A Proposal for Philosophy of Cognitive and Social Sciences. Constructivist Foundations 14(1): 42–55. https://cepa.info/5586
Context: Most recent attempts to define cognition dialectically lack the philosophical completeness necessary to explain neurocognitive and mental processes. Problem: Under what conditions could neurophenomenology be thought of as dialectical and what would be the implications of such a conception for contemporary issues such as “social cognition” and phenomenological subjectivity? Method: I assess dialectical approaches to neurocognitive processes and mind mostly within the recent neurophenomenological literature and provide reasons as to why these approaches could be further improved using Hegel’s conception of dialectical processes. Results: As suggested in the context of research on extended cognition, mostly by Gallagher and Crisafi, a cognitively shaped understanding of Hegel’s philosophy allows us to understand how neurophenomenology can be conceptualized dialectically. It allows us to conceive precisely of how dialectical processes can help shape our understanding of cognition from individual neurocognitive operations to socially embedded processes. A dialectical interpretation of Varela’s conception of neurocognitive processes can help achieve the endeavor of recent sociological work to understand the “continuity” from individual to social “entities” through a “relational ontology.” This amounts to expanding, through a neurodialectical framework, Gallagher’s research on extended cognition as well as articulating it with his most recent conception of “decentered” cognition. Implications: Neurodialectics has straightforward implications for phenomenological understandings of subjectivity as well as for recent sociological research: in both cases, it can provide us with a philosophically meaningful and empirically sustainable framework. In particular, it could help philosophically expand Gallagher’s “decentered” model of brainhood. Constructivist Content: I argue in favor of a general philosophical perspective, the neurodialectical one, stressing the “primacy of moulding on being.”
Zaslawski N. & Arminjon M. (2018) Shaun Gallagher and the Sciences of the Mind: Recontextualizing “Decentered” Cognition. Constructivist Foundations 14(1): 1–8. https://cepa.info/5577
Context: Shaun Gallagher’s work is very influential in contemporary philosophy, especially when it comes to the mind, to philosophical issues raised by developmental psychology, and to intersubjectivity. Problem: Classical cognitivism” has been, and often still is dominating the sciences of the mind. The reasons for this dominance include being implementable on computers, being consistent with Darwinism, and being allegedly experimentally testable. However, this dominance could just as well be a historical phase as cognitivism is disconnected from biological, anthropological, and neuroscientific research. Method: We historically and epistemologically contextualize how Gallagher contributed to bringing the body and subjectivity back to the center of the sciences of the mind by focusing on two examples: theory of mind and evolutionary psychology. Results: Both contemporary epistemologists and Gallagher’s work indicate why classical cognitivism provides a flawed model of cognition, especially when it comes to its explanatory scope: embodiment, subjectivity, and intersubjectivity, among other things, are fundamentally mistreated by cognitivism. Implications: Gallagher helped to structure what Andler calls “heterodoxical” approaches to cognition by conceptualizing a unifying framework, the so-called “E-approaches.” This unification has the major implication of leading Gallagher to a model in which cognition is “decentered,” which helps tackle the philosophical issues one might encounter when narrowing down philosophy of cognition. Constructivist content: We apply E-approaches to the philosophy of cognition, psychology and social sciences.
Zitterbarth W. (1991) Der Erlanger Konstruktivismus in seiner Beziehung zum Konstruktiven Realismus. In: Peschl M. F. (ed.) Formen des Konstruktivismus in Diskussion. WUV–Universitätsverlag, Wien: 73–87. https://cepa.info/4247
Excerpt: Betrachtet man neuere Veröffentlichungen zum Radikalen Konstruktivismus und dessen Entstehungsgeschichte – und ich möchte im Rahmen meiner Ausführungen den “konstruktiven Realismus” als eine legitime Weiterentwicklung radikal konstruktivistischen Gedankengutes auffassen –, so gewinnt man den Eindruck, als gehöre der Erlanger Konstruktivismus weder in die Ahnengalerie noch zur unmittelbaren Verwandtschaft seines radikalen Namensvetters. Dieser Eindruck verstärkt sich noch, wenn man in einer sorgfältigen und kenntnisreichen Arbeit von Gebhard Rusch liest, daß der Ausdruck “Radikaler Konstruktivismus” in “keinerlei systematischem Zusammenhang mit dem Konstruktivismus der Erlanger Schule um Paul Lorenzen [steht].” Handelt es sich bei den beiden Konstruktivismen also bloß um eine auf oberflächlichen Ähnlichkeiten beruhende, mehr oder minder zufällige Namensübereinstimmung? Ich denke es läßt sich zeigen, daß dem nicht so ist, und ich will dieser Aufgabe hier in zwei Schritten nachkommen. Zuerst möchte ich auf einen historischen Zusammenhang beider Ansätze zu sprechen kommen, der bisher völlig unbeachtet blieb, anschließend will ich die Frage nach dem Zusammenhang auch systematisch behandeln.
Zitterbarth W. (1998) Erkenntnistheorie und Repräsentation. In: Fischer H. R. (ed.) Die Wirklichkeit des Konstruktivismus: Zur Auseinandersetzung um ein neues Paradigma. Second edition. Carl-Auer-Systeme, Heidelberg: 93–102.