Key word "glasersfeld"
Bettoni M. C. (2007) The Yerkish Language: From Operational Methodology to Chimpanzee Communication. Constructivist Foundations 2(2-3): 32–38. https://cepa.info/26
Bettoni M. C.
(
2007)
The Yerkish Language: From Operational Methodology to Chimpanzee Communication.
Constructivist Foundations 2(2-3): 32–38.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/26
Purpose: Yerkish is an artificial language created in 1971 for the specific purpose of exploring the linguistic potential of nonhuman primates. The aim of this paper is to remind the research community of some important issues and concepts related to Yerkish that seem to have been forgotten or appear to be distorted. These are, particularly, its success, its promising aspects for future research and last but not least that it was Ernst von Glasersfeld who invented Yerkish: he coined the term “lexigrams,” created the first 120 of them and designed the grammar that regulated their combination. Design: The first part of this paper begins with a short outline of the context in which the Yerkish language originated: the original LANA project. It continues by presenting the language itself in more detail: first, its design, focusing on its “lexigrams” and its “correlational” grammar (the connective functions or “correlators” and the combinations of lexigrams, or “correlations”), and then its use by the chimpanzee Lana in formulating sentences. The second part gives a brief introduction to the foundation of Yerkish in Silvio Ceccato’s Operational Methodology, particularly his idea of the correlational structure of thought and concludes with the main insights that can be derived from the Yerkish experiment seen in the light of Operational Methodology. Findings: Lana’s success in language learning and the success of Yerkish during the past decades are probably due to the characteristics of Yerkish, particularly its foundation in operational methodology. The operation of correlation could be what constitutes thinking in a chimpanzee and an attentional system could be what delivers the mental content that correlation assembles into triads and networks. Research implications: Since no other assessment or explanation of Lana’s performances has considered these foundational issues (findings), a new research project or program should validate the above-mentioned hypotheses, particularly the correlational structure of chimpanzee thinking.
Bettoni M. C. (2008) The Illusion of Society. Constructivist Foundations 3(2): 68–69. https://constructivist.info/3/2/068
Bettoni M. C.
(
2008)
The Illusion of Society.
Constructivist Foundations 3(2): 68–69.
Fulltext at https://constructivist.info/3/2/068
Open peer commentary on the target article “Who Conceives of Society?” by Ernst von Glasersfeld. First paragraph: Issues such as social interaction and communication play an essential role in my recent approach to knowledge management called “Knowledge Cooperation”, conceived as “the participative cultivation of knowledge in a voluntary, informal social group”. Radical Constructivism (RC) provides a substantial support to the foundations of this approach, which aims at equilibrating intellectual and social capital. So I warmly welcome Ernst von Glasersfeld’s clarification of the constructivist position in regard to “society.”
Bettoni M. C. (2011) Constructing a Beginning in 1985. Constructivist Foundations 6(2): 184–189. https://constructivist.info/6/2/184
Bettoni M. C.
(
2011)
Constructing a Beginning in 1985.
Constructivist Foundations 6(2): 184–189.
Fulltext at https://constructivist.info/6/2/184
Context: Meeting Ernst von Glasersfeld for the first time in 1985, when about 70% of his work had still to be conceived, written and published, was a great stroke of fortune for me; it was based on my collaboration with Silvio Ceccato that had started in 1981 and it profoundly influenced my contributions to radical constructivism in the following 25 years of our friendship. Problem: Presenting the details of how it all began can shed a light on the development of constructivist ideas. Method: Anecdotes from 1979 to 1985 about how I came to meet Silvio Ceccato in Milan in 1981 and the influence of these events on preparing the 1985 meeting with Ernst von Glasersfeld, also in Milan. Results: The article describes the timeline of 50 years of publications by von Glasersfeld, an anecdote about a connection between Ceccato and the University of Zurich in the 60s, the attempt to present Ceccato’s ideas as compatible and complementary with the neuroscience discourse in 1985, von Glasersfeld’s opinion about this attempt, and this attempt’s potential influence on the emergence of a new concept in neuroscience, “EEG microstates.” Implications: The events and facts reported in the article help us to understand some aspects of an early phase in the development of radical constructivism, especially the relationship between Ceccato, von Glasersfeld and other members of the Italian Operational School such as Bruna Zonta, Felice Accame, and the author himself.
Bettoni M., Schiller G. & Bernhard W. (2008) Weak Ties Cooperation in the CoRe Knowledge Network. In: Harorimana D. & Watkins D. (eds.) Proceedings of the 9th European Conference on Knowledge Management, Southampton Solent University, Southampton, UK, 4–5 September 2008. Academic Publishing, Reading: 59–66.
Bettoni M., Schiller G. & Bernhard W.
(
2008)
Weak Ties Cooperation in the CoRe Knowledge Network.
In: Harorimana D. & Watkins D. (eds.) Proceedings of the 9th European Conference on Knowledge Management, Southampton Solent University, Southampton, UK, 4–5 September 2008. Academic Publishing, Reading: 59–66.
The discipline of Knowledge Management (KM) has been dealing with the issue of knowledge flow for almost 20 years … Unfortunately in all these and similar investigations an essential component was missing or not explicitly stated and discussed: the fundamental principle or view that every person is inseparably bound to his or her knowledge … The foundation of this principle is Radical Constructivism (von Glasersfeld 1995), which anchors the concept of knowledge more than ever in the human being
Birbaumer N. (2008) Does Brain Science Render Constructivism Superfluous? Constructivist Foundations 3(2): 86–87. https://constructivist.info/3/2/086
Birbaumer N.
(
2008)
Does Brain Science Render Constructivism Superfluous?
Constructivist Foundations 3(2): 86–87.
Fulltext at https://constructivist.info/3/2/086
Open peer commentary on the target article “Who Conceives of Society?” by Ernst von Glasersfeld. Excerpt: In the face of modern neuroscience we should give up on constructivism, even more so on radical constructivism, and stick to the physical and psychological reality given in science and daily life, even if it is the brain’s illusion from associative networks. The illusion of constructivism may hurt!
Boden M. A. (2010) Against Constructivism. Constructivist Foundations 6(1): 84–89. https://constructivist.info/6/1/084
Boden M. A.
(
2010)
Against Constructivism.
Constructivist Foundations 6(1): 84–89.
Fulltext at https://constructivist.info/6/1/084
Context: Radical Constructivism is an issue that deeply divides the cognitive science community: most researchers reject it, but an increasing number do not. Problem: Constructivists stress that our knowledge starts from experience. Some (“ontic” constructivists) deny the existence of a mind-independent world, while others (“radical” constructivists) claim merely that, if such a world exists, we can know nothing about it. Both positions conflict with scientific realism. It is not clear that the conflict can be resolved. Method: This paper uses philosophical argument to ask whether constructivism can be rationally preferred over realism in science. Results: Ontic constructivism cannot be disproved by any knock-down argument. Nevertheless, it is irrational to accept it, because it ignores the strategy of “inference to the best explanation”: realism is the best explanation of the successes of science. Radical constructivism, too, fails to explain these successes. Some radical constructivists have tried to offer theories more sympathetic to realism. For instance, Ernst von Glasersfeld sees science as a coherent ordering of experience, and appeals to Piagetian psychology as support. There are close similarities. But Piaget was also caught in a constructivist anti-realism, despite his attempt to evade it. Implications: The constructivist’s claim that scientific concepts and theories are generated by human minds is correct. But this important insight should not be used to deny realism, which is the best explanation of the many undeniable successes of science and engineering.
Braffort P. (2007) Ernst Glasersfeld’s First Scientific Paper. Constructivist Foundations 2(2-3): 12–17. https://cepa.info/22
Braffort P.
(
2007)
Ernst Glasersfeld’s First Scientific Paper.
Constructivist Foundations 2(2-3): 12–17.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/22
Purpose: At Silvio Ceccato’s suggestion, I invited Ernst von Glasersfeld to the “Séminaire Leibniz” which took place in Brussels, in February 1961. The paper he delivered then, Operational Semantics: Analysis of Meaning in Terms of Operations, was included in a Euratom internal report and is published here for the first time. Conclusion: These early works clearly show von Glasersfeld’s methodological and philosophical coherence as well as his faithfulness to Ceccato’s endeavour.
Braffort P. (2011) Ernst von Glasersfeld’s Legacy Is Alive and Well in France and Italy! Constructivist Foundations 6(2): 139. https://constructivist.info/6/2/139
Braffort P.
(
2011)
Ernst von Glasersfeld’s Legacy Is Alive and Well in France and Italy!
Constructivist Foundations 6(2): 139.
Fulltext at https://constructivist.info/6/2/139
Upshot: Paul Braffort was in charge of the research department GRISA (Groupe de Recherches sur l’Information Scientifique Automatique) in EURATOM when Ernst von Glasersfeld joined Silvio Ceccato’s group in the early 1960s. With these responsibilities he provided the initial funding for the work on language analysis that later Ernst brought to the US. In his essay Braffort describes von Glasersfeld’s professional involvements in France and Italy.
Brier S. (2009) Cybersemiotic Pragmaticism and Constructivism. Constructivist Foundations 5(1): 19-39. https://constructivist.info/5/1/019
Brier S.
(
2009)
Cybersemiotic Pragmaticism and Constructivism.
Constructivist Foundations 5(1): 19-39.
Fulltext at https://constructivist.info/5/1/019
Context: Radical constructivism claims that we have no final truth criteria for establishing one ontology over another. This leaves us with the question of how we can come to know anything in a viable manner. According to von Glasersfeld, radical constructivism is a theory of knowledge rather than a philosophy of the world in itself because we do not have access to a human-independent world. He considers knowledge as the ordering of experience to cope with situations in a satisfactory way. Problem: Von Foerster and Krippendorff show that the central goal of a constructivist theory of knowing must be to find a way of putting the knower into a known that is constructed so as to keep the knower, as well as the knowing process, viable in practice. Method: The conceptual and philosophical analysis of present theories and their necessary prerequisites suggests that such foundation for viable knowing can be built on the analysis of what the ontological prerequisites are for establishing viable observing, cognition, communication and observer-communicators, and communication media and vehicles. Results: The moment an observer chooses to accept his/her own embodied conscious presence in this world as well as language, he/she must accept other humans as partly independently existing conversation partners; if knowledge and knowing has to make sense, he/she must also accept as prerequisites for our observation and conversation a pre-linguistic reality from which our bodies come and which our conversation is often about. Furthermore, we can no longer claim that there is a reality that we do not know anything about: From being here in conversation, we know that the world can produce more or less stable embodied consciousnesses that can exchange and construct conceptual meanings through embodied conversations and actions that last over time and exist in space-time and mind, and are correlated to our embodied practices. We can also see that our communication works through signs for all living systems as well as in human language, understood as a structured and progressively developed system of communication. The prerequisite for this social semiotic production of meaning is the fourfold “semiotic star of cybersemiotics,” which includes at least four different worlds: our bodies, the combination of society, culture and language, our consciousness, and also an outer nature. Implications: The semiotic star in cybersemiotics claims that the internal subjective, the intersubjective linguistic, our living bodies, and nature are irreducible and equally necessary as epistemological prerequisites for knowing. The viable reality of any of them cannot be denied without self-refuting paradoxes. There is an obvious connectedness between the four worlds, which Peirce called “synechism.” It also points to Peirce’s conclusion that logic and rationality are part of the process of semiosis, and that meaning in the form of semiosis is a fundamental aspect of reality, not just a construction in our heads. Erratum: The paper erroneously refers to “pleroma.” The correct term is “plemora.”
Key words: ontology,
embodiment,
philosophy of observing,
second-order cybernetics,
autopoiesis,
semiotics,
language,
phenomenology,
radical constructivism,
Edmund Husserl,
Charles Sanders Peirce,
George Spencer-Brown
Buchinger E. (2012) Luhmann and the Constructivist Heritage: A Critical Reflection. Constructivist Foundations 8(1): 19–28. https://constructivist.info/8/1/019
Buchinger E.
(
2012)
Luhmann and the Constructivist Heritage: A Critical Reflection.
Constructivist Foundations 8(1): 19–28.
Fulltext at https://constructivist.info/8/1/019
Context: Luhmann’s theory of autopoietic social systems is increasingly receiving attention in the scholarly dispute about constructivism. Problem: The paper explores the transition from Kant’s “transcendental/empirical” to Luhmann’s “system/environment” distinction to provide a deepened understanding of Luhmann’s constructivist approach. Method: Luhmann’s construction of reality via the system/environment distinction is discussed with respect to preceding concepts provided by philosophical and system/cybernetic scholars such as Kant, Husserl, Piaget, von Glasersfeld, von Foerster, and Maturana & Varela. The innovativeness of Luhmann’s approach is then critically evaluated. Results: Luhmann’s contribution to constructivism is innovative only in the context of his stringent theory architecture of autopoietic meaning-based systems. Implications: The text is a contribution to the positioning of this approach as part of the philosophical and systems/cybernetics constructivist heritage.
Export result page as:
·
·
·
·
·
·
·
·