Toggle navigation
CEPA.INFO
FAQ
BROWSE
Authors
Constructivist Approaches
Background Disciplines
Reading Lists
Latest Fulltext Additions
LOGIN
Search Results
Publications Found:
262
·
Show All Abstracts
·
Highlight Matches
Search CEPA
» Help with Search
fulltext:"Man, having within himself an imagined world of lines and numbers, operates in it with abstractions just as God in the universe, did with reality"
fulltext:"Man, having within himself an imagined world of lines and numbers, operates in it with abstractions just as God in the universe, did with reality"
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????? ORDER BY 3989
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/?????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????) ORDER BY 7543
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/?????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????' ORDER BY 4180
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/?????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????') ORDER BY 4953
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/?????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????' ORDER BY 7206
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????? ORDER BY 8748
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x2f�������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������B
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x2f���������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������
By default, Find returns all publications that contain the words in the surnames of their author, in their titles, or in their years. For example,
Maturana
finds all publications authored by Maturana and publications that have "Maturana" in their title
Maturana 1974
finds all publications authored by Maturana in 1974
You can directly search for a reference by copy-pasting it. For example,
Glasersfeld E. von (1974) Jean Piaget and the radical constructivist epistemology
Unless a word (or phrase) if prefixed with a minus (-) it must be present in all results. Examples:
Glasersfeld Varela
shows all publications Ernst von Glasersfeld and Francisco Varela wrote together.
Glasersfeld "Jean Piaget"
finds all publications with
Glasersfeld
and
Jean Piaget
in it.
Prefix with
-
to indicate that this word must not be present in any result:
cognition -biology
will find entries that have
cognition
in the title but not
biology
.
Enter the surname of an author and a year to find all publications the author wrote in that year:
Glasersfeld 1995
presents all publications Ernst von Glasersfeld published in 1995.
Use
*
to match any characters:
constructivis*
matches constructivism and constructivist.
Enclose phrases between double quotes
"
to force phrase search:
"biology of cognition"
lists only the publications containing this phrase. Without the double quotes it will return all publications containing "biology" and all publications containing "cognition".
All the searches above match author names, titles and years. You can also address single fields:
author:glasersfeld title:reality
shows publications von Glasersfeld wrote on reality;
abstract:second-order
searches all abstracts for "second-order";
editor:Watzlawick
finds all books edited by Watzlawick.
Note there is no space after the colon.
Attention: Words of three letters and less are ignored.
"Not one, not two"
will return no result although there is
Varela's paper
of this title.
Williams S. R. (1991) Review of Understanding Computers and Cognition by T. Winograd & F. Flores. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 11(1): 57–60.
Williams S. R.
(
1991
)
Review of Understanding Computers and
Cognition
by T. Winograd & F. Flores
.
Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology
11(1): 57–60.
Copy Citation
Wilson A. D. & Golonka S. (2013) Embodied cognition is not what you think it is. Frontiers in Psycholology 4: 58.
Wilson A. D.
&
Golonka S.
(
2013
)
Embodied
cognition
is not what you think it is
.
Frontiers in Psycholology
4: 58.
Copy Citation
Wilson M. (2002) Six views of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 9(4): 625–636. https://cepa.info/4970
Wilson M.
(
2002
)
Six views of embodied
cognition
.
Psychonomic Bulletin & Review
9(4): 625–636.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/4970
Copy Citation
The emerging viewpoint of embodied
cognition
holds that cognitive processes are deeply rooted in the body’s interactions with the world. This position actually houses a number of distinct claims, some of which are more controversial than others. This paper distinguishes and evaluates the following six claims: (1)
cognition
is situated; (2)
cognition
is time-pressured; (3) we off-load cognitive work onto the environment; (4) the environment is part of the cognitive system; (5)
cognition
is for action; (6) offline
cognition
is body based. Of these, the first three and the fifth appear to be at least partially true, and their usefulness is best evaluated in terms of the range of their applicability. The fourth claim, I argue, is deeply problematic. The sixth claim has received the least attention in the literature on embodied
cognition
, but it may in fact be the best documented and most powerful of the six claims.
Key words:
Time pressure
,
implicit memory
,
cognitive architecture
,
early human
,
situate cognition
Winograd T. & Flores F. (1987) Cognition as a biological phenomenon. Chapter 4 in: Understanding computers and cognition: A new foundation for design. Addison-Wesley, Reading MA: 38–53. https://cepa.info/5789
Winograd T.
&
Flores F.
(
1987
)
Cognition
as a biological phenomenon
.
Chapter 4 in:
Understanding computers and
cognition
: A new foundation for design
. Addison-Wesley, Reading MA: 38–53.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/5789
Copy Citation
Excerpt:
The rationalistic orientation of our prior training in science and technology made the foundations of hermeneutics and phenomenology nearly inaccessible to us. Before we could become open to their relevance and importance we needed to take a preliminary step towards unconcealing the tradition in which we lived, recognizing that it was in fact open to serious question. For us, this first step came through the work of Humberto Maturana, a biologist who has been concerned with understanding how biological processes can give rise to the phenomena of
cognition
and language.
Winograd T. & Flores F. (1987) On Understanding Computers and Cognition: A New Foundation for Design: A response to the reviews. Artificial Intelligence 31(2): 250–261. https://cepa.info/5324
Winograd T.
&
Flores F.
(
1987
)
On Understanding Computers and
Cognition
: A New Foundation for Design: A response to the reviews
.
Artificial Intelligence
31(2): 250–261.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/5324
Copy Citation
Excerpt:
In Understanding Computers and
Cognition
, we presented a theory of language, on which we base our understanding of
cognition
and of computers. It includes some basic assertions about how language works […] The reviews collected here offer a striking validation of this theory. The same piece of language (in this case, our book) produced four widely different understandings, each generated within the background of a particular listener. The important issue is not that different reviewers “liked” the book more or less, but that they heard it as addresing different concerns in different ongoing conversations. We will begin our response by examining their interpretations and the backgrounds in which they arose.
Wright C. D. (2008) Embodied cognition: Grounded until further notice. British Journal of Psychology 99: 157–164. https://cepa.info/4512
Wright C. D.
(
2008
)
Embodied
cognition
: Grounded until further notice
.
British Journal of Psychology
99: 157–164.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/4512
Copy Citation
Excerpt:
Review of: Grounding
cognition
: The role of perception and action in memory, language, and thinking, By Diane Pecher and Rolf A. Zwaan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005, ISBN-13: 978–0–5218–3464–3
Xu F. (2011) Rational constructivism, statistical inference, and core cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34(3): 151–152.
Xu F.
(
2011
)
Rational constructivism, statistical inference, and core
cognition
.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences
34(3): 151–152.
Copy Citation
I make two points in this commentary on Carey (2009). First, it may be too soon to conclude that core
cognition
is innate. Recent advances in computational cognitive science and developmental psychology suggest possible mechanisms for developing inductive biases. Second, there is another possible answer to Fodor’s challenge – if concepts are merely mental tokens, then cognitive scientists should spend their time on developing a theory of belief fixation instead.
Zahidi K. & Myin E. (2016) Radically enactive numerical cognition. In: Etzelmüller G. & Twews C. (eds.) Embodiment in evolution and culture. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen: 57–71. https://cepa.info/7391
Zahidi K.
&
Myin E.
(
2016
)
Radically enactive numerical
cognition
.
In: Etzelmüller G. & Twews C. (eds.)
Embodiment in evolution and culture
. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen: 57–71.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/7391
Copy Citation
We deal with the general question of how culture affects
cognition
by looking at numerical
cognition
. After presenting radical enactivism, according to which contentful
cognition
arises only with the emergence of truth telling practices, we confront recent research about the origins of numerical
cognition
. We contest readings of some of the empirical data, according to which numerical
cognition
predates culture. We argue that REC-friendly interpretations of the data are not only possible but preferable, as they avoid the staunch theoretical problems which plague cognitivist readings.
Zaslawski N. & Arminjon M. (2018) Shaun Gallagher and the Sciences of the Mind: Recontextualizing “Decentered” Cognition. Constructivist Foundations 14(1): 1–8. https://cepa.info/5577
Zaslawski N.
&
Arminjon M.
(
2018
)
Shaun Gallagher and the Sciences of the Mind: Recontextualizing “Decentered”
Cognition
.
Constructivist Foundations
14(1): 1–8.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/5577
Copy Citation
Context:
Shaun Gallagher’s work is very influential in contemporary philosophy, especially when it comes to the mind, to philosophical issues raised by developmental psychology, and to intersubjectivity.
Problem:
Classical cognitivism” has been, and often still is dominating the sciences of the mind. The reasons for this dominance include being implementable on computers, being consistent with Darwinism, and being allegedly experimentally testable. However, this dominance could just as well be a historical phase as cognitivism is disconnected from biological, anthropological, and neuroscientific research.
Method:
We historically and epistemologically contextualize how Gallagher contributed to bringing the body and subjectivity back to the center of the sciences of the mind by focusing on two examples: theory of mind and evolutionary psychology.
Results:
Both contemporary epistemologists and Gallagher’s work indicate why classical cognitivism provides a flawed model of
cognition
, especially when it comes to its explanatory scope: embodiment, subjectivity, and intersubjectivity, among other things, are fundamentally mistreated by cognitivism.
Implications:
Gallagher helped to structure what Andler calls “heterodoxical” approaches to
cognition
by conceptualizing a unifying framework, the so-called “E-approaches.” This unification has the major implication of leading Gallagher to a model in which
cognition
is “decentered,” which helps tackle the philosophical issues one might encounter when narrowing down philosophy of
cognition
.
Constructivist content:
We apply E-approaches to the philosophy of
cognition
, psychology and social sciences.
Key words:
Philosophy of mind
,
philosophy of cognitive science
,
history of science
,
embodiment
,
E-approaches
Ziemke T. (2004) Embodied AI as science: Models of embodied cognition, embodied models of cognition, or both? In: Iida F., Pfeifer R., Steels L. & Kuniyoshi Y. (eds.) Embodied artificial intelligence. Springer-Verlag, Heidelberg: 27–36. https://cepa.info/7227
Ziemke T.
(
2004
)
Embodied AI as science: Models of embodied
cognition
, embodied models of
cognition
, or both?
.
In: Iida F., Pfeifer R., Steels L. & Kuniyoshi Y. (eds.)
Embodied artificial intelligence
. Springer-Verlag, Heidelberg: 27–36.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/7227
Copy Citation
This paper discusses the identity of embodied AI, i.e. it asks the question exactly what it is that makes AI research embodied. From an engineering perspective, it is fairly clear that embodied AI is about robotic, i.e. physically embodied systems. From the scientific perspective of AI as building models of natural
cognition
or intelligence, however, things are less clear. On the one hand embodied AI seems to be about physically embodied, i.e. robotic models of
cognition
. On the other hand the term ‘embodied’ seems to signify the type of intelligence modeled and/or the conception of (embodied)
cognition
that is underlying the modeling. In either case, it appears that embodied AI, as it currently stands, might be too narrowly conceived since each of these perspectives is addressed only partially.
Export result page as:
CF Format
·
APA
·
BibTex
·
EndNote
·
Harvard
·
MLA
·
Nature
·
RIS
·
Science
Page
1
2
...
25
26
27
Please provide us with your
feedback/evaluation/suggestions