Toggle navigation
CEPA.INFO
FAQ
BROWSE
Authors
Constructivist Approaches
Background Disciplines
Reading Lists
Latest Fulltext Additions
LOGIN
Search Results
Publications Found:
14
·
Show All Abstracts
·
Highlight Matches
Search CEPA
» Help with Search
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x2f���������������������������������������������������������������������������������B
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x2f������������������������������������������������������������������������������
fulltext:"Man, having within himself an imagined world of lines and numbers, operates in it with abstractions just as God in the universe, did with reality"
fulltext:"Man, having within himself an imagined world of lines and numbers, operates in it with abstractions just as God in the universe, did with reality"
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????? ORDER BY 3989
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/?????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????) ORDER BY 7543
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/?????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????' ORDER BY 4180
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/?????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????') ORDER BY 4953
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/?????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????' ORDER BY 7206
fulltext:maturana9999922unionselectunhex(hex(version()))--22x22=22x/????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????????? ORDER BY 8748
By default, Find returns all publications that contain the words in the surnames of their author, in their titles, or in their years. For example,
Maturana
finds all publications authored by Maturana and publications that have "Maturana" in their title
Maturana 1974
finds all publications authored by Maturana in 1974
You can directly search for a reference by copy-pasting it. For example,
Glasersfeld E. von (1974) Jean Piaget and the radical constructivist epistemology
Unless a word (or phrase) if prefixed with a minus (-) it must be present in all results. Examples:
Glasersfeld Varela
shows all publications Ernst von Glasersfeld and Francisco Varela wrote together.
Glasersfeld "Jean Piaget"
finds all publications with
Glasersfeld
and
Jean Piaget
in it.
Prefix with
-
to indicate that this word must not be present in any result:
cognition -biology
will find entries that have
cognition
in the title but not
biology
.
Enter the surname of an author and a year to find all publications the author wrote in that year:
Glasersfeld 1995
presents all publications Ernst von Glasersfeld published in 1995.
Use
*
to match any characters:
constructivis*
matches constructivism and constructivist.
Enclose phrases between double quotes
"
to force phrase search:
"biology of cognition"
lists only the publications containing this phrase. Without the double quotes it will return all publications containing "biology" and all publications containing "cognition".
All the searches above match author names, titles and years. You can also address single fields:
author:glasersfeld title:reality
shows publications von Glasersfeld wrote on reality;
abstract:second-order
searches all abstracts for "second-order";
editor:Watzlawick
finds all books edited by Watzlawick.
Note there is no space after the colon.
Attention: Words of three letters and less are ignored.
"Not one, not two"
will return no result although there is
Varela's paper
of this title.
Ashby W. R. (1967) The place of the brain in the natural world. Currents in Modern Biology 1: 95–104.
Ashby W. R.
(
1967
)
The place of the brain in the natural world
.
Currents in Modern Biology
1: 95–104.
Copy Citation
A great deal is known already about the brain, but most of our knowledge of it is still in the form of experimental and observational facts, With the growing interest in the brain’s more general properties, however, such as in “artificial intelligence” in its various forms. the time has come for an abstract formulation of the nature of”brain”. a formulation suitable for a direct translation to the computer or hardware, The paper gives such a formulation on the basis of set theory and the concept of the state-determined system.
Bateson G. (1967) Cybernetic explanation. The American Behavioral Scientist 10(8): 29–32. https://cepa.info/2726
Bateson G.
(
1967
)
Cybernetic explanation
.
The American Behavioral Scientist
10(8): 29–32.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/2726
Copy Citation
Ceccato S. (1967) Concepts for a new systematics. Information Storage and Retrieval 3(4): 193–214. https://cepa.info/6385
Ceccato S.
(
1967
)
Concepts for a new systematics
.
Information Storage and Retrieval
3(4): 193–214.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/6385
Copy Citation
Foerster H. von (1967) Biological principles of information storage and retrieval. In: Kent A. (ed.) Electronic handling of information: Testing and evaluation. Academic Press, London: 123–147. https://cepa.info/1628
Foerster H. von
(
1967
)
Biological principles of information storage and retrieval
.
In: Kent A. (ed.)
Electronic handling of information: Testing and evaluation
. Academic Press, London: 123–147.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/1628
Copy Citation
Foerster H. von (1967) Computation in neural nets. Currents in Modern Biology 1: 47–93.
Foerster H. von
(
1967
)
Computation in neural nets
.
Currents in Modern Biology
1: 47–93.
Copy Citation
A mathematical apparatus is developed that deals with networks of elements which are connected to each other by well defined connection rules and which perform well defined operations on their inputs. The output of these elements either is transmitted to other elements in the network or – should they be terminal elements – represents the outcome of the computation of the network. The discussion is confined to such rules of connection between elements and their operational modalities as they appear to have anatomical and physiological counter parts in neural tissue. The great latitude given today in the interpretation of nervous activity with regard to what constitutes the “signal” is accounted for by giving the mathematical apparatus the necessary and sufficient latitude to cope with various interpretations. Special attention is given to a mathematical formulation of structural and functional properties of networks that compute invariants in the distribution of their stimuli.
Foerster H. von (1967) Time and memory. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 138(2): 866–873. https://cepa.info/1626
Foerster H. von
(
1967
)
Time and memory
.
Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences
138(2): 866–873.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/1626
Copy Citation
Günther G. (1967) Time, timeless logic and self‐referential systems. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 138(2): 396–406. https://cepa.info/5316
Günther G.
(
1967
)
Time, timeless logic and self‐referential systems
.
Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences
138(2): 396–406.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/5316
Copy Citation
Günther G. (1967) Time, timeless logic, and self-referential systems. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 138: 396–406. https://cepa.info/3646
Günther G.
(
1967
)
Time, timeless logic, and self-referential systems
.
Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences
138: 396–406.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/3646
Copy Citation
Excerpt:
For more than two millennia, all Western scientific thought has rested on the methodological principle of two-valuedness dividing all reality into an objective and a subjective component. The division was assumed to be exhaustive. The existence of a third value of basic ontological significance was expressly denied. The ensuing system of logic not only posed the questions but also circumscribed the range of permissible answers. One of the two available values was considered to be designative, and the other had to be nondesignative in order to obtain a set of laws interpretable in ontological terms. The designative value was called positive; it pointed to the purely objective aspect of the universe. And since the non-designative or negative value could not point at anything, the trend of all Western science, based on this system of logic, has been one of progressive objectivation to the exclusion of all traces of “subjectivity” – which are implied in the nondesignative value.
Günther G. & Foerster H. von (1967) The logical structure of evolution and emanation. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 138(2): 874–891. https://cepa.info/1627
Günther G.
&
Foerster H. von
(
1967
)
The logical structure of evolution and emanation
.
Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences
138(2): 874–891.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/1627
Copy Citation
Piaget J. (1967) Conclusion. Chapter 5 in: La construction du réel chez l’enfant. Sixth edition. Originally published in 1937. Delachaux & Niestlé, Neuchâtel: 307–342. https://cepa.info/6180
Piaget J.
(
1967
)
Conclusion
.
Chapter 5 in:
La construction du réel chez l’enfant. Sixth edition. Originally published in 1937
. Delachaux & Niestlé, Neuchâtel: 307–342.
Fulltext at https://cepa.info/6180
Copy Citation
Ce chapitre de conclusion n’offre pas seulement une brève mais lumineuse synthèse des résultats et réflexions des chapitres précédents ainsi que de l’ouvrage sur La naissance de l’intelligence (JP36) auquel La construction du réel est étroitement lié, mais un premier exposé d’ensemble des recherches conduites par Piaget et ses collaboratrices Inhelder et Szeminska sur la pensée concrète de l’enfant (développement des quantités physiques – substance, poids, volume – et des représentations spatiales et temporelles). Une comparaison peut ainsi être établie entre les étapes de la construction de l’objet matériel (mais non pas de son identité logique), du champ spatial et du champ temporel pendant les vingt premiers mois de la vie de l’enfant, et la construction des notions opératoires de substance, de poids, de volume, d’espace et de temps qui s’achèvera entre 7 et 10 ans environ – une comparaison qui permet une première détermination des raisons d’un tel décalage (passage du plan de l’action sensori-motrice au plan des représentions “pures”, c’est-à-dire non directement reliées à l’action, passage donc de la logique de l’action à la logique de la pensée “représentative” et “socialisée”). Cette conclusion d’un ouvrage qui est une clé majeure du constructivisme piagétien a ainsi pour intérêt secondaire non négligeable de permettre de prendre connaissance des premières réflexions de Piaget relativement aux résultats des travaux encore en cours sur le développement de la pensée opératoire concrète. De ce fait, elle permet de prendre la pleine mesure des travaux et réflexions ultérieurs qui seront nécessaires pour atteindre des degrés d’explication supérieure à celle proposée à la fin des années trente, mais aussi jusqu’aux années 1940, quant au problème de la genèse des structures opératoires, elles-mêmes explicatives des propriétés de cette première forme de pensée rationnelle.
Export result page as:
CF Format
·
APA
·
BibTex
·
EndNote
·
Harvard
·
MLA
·
Nature
·
RIS
·
Science
Page
1
2
Please provide us with your
feedback/evaluation/suggestions